مجموعة اليسر للتدريب والاستشارات تأمل من زوارها الكرام المشاركة في الاستطلاعات التي تجريها بفعالية نظرا لفائدتها العالية
مجموعة اليسر للتدريب والاستشارات هي شركة تضامن لبنانية مسجلة تحت الرقم 489 تتنشط في مجال الدورات التدريبية والمؤتمرات العلمية والتربوية والاجتماعية والادارية والثقافية والتنمية والارشاد الاسري والاجتماعي ، واصدار المنشورات المتخصصة ، وتقديم الاستشارات في المجالات المذكورة وتوقيع الاتفاقيات مع الجامعات والمؤسسات والشركات الوطنية والعالمية على انواعها والقيام بالاستطلاعات والابحاث العلمية والدراسات المتخصصة في لبنان والخارج - نتمنى لكم زيارة ممتعة

10‏/12‏/2010

Sociology of Knowledge

 Sociology of Knowledge
The Sociology of Knowledge edited by Volker Meja and Nico Stehr (The 
International Library of Critical Writings  in  Sociology,  12:  Edward  Elgar) 
These two hefty volumes manages to collect together a full critical outline 
of the central questions and methods of the sociology of knowledge, 
including prospects for its revival in sociological discourse. 
Excerpt: from introduction 
Development, Status and Prospects of the Sociology of Knowledge 
The sociology of knowledge, although a recognized sociological specialty since the 
late 1920s, is often regarded as a unique field of study, which, to a greater degree than 
other areas of sociology, has fascinated  scholars throughout the social and human 
sciences.' Because of its claim that the discovery of truth is socially and historically 
conditioned, the sociology of knowledge has at times been regarded as a kind of 
Copernican revolution in the analysis of cultural products.' While the older sociology 
of knowledge epitomized by Karl Mannheim, asked how the social location of 
individuals and groups shapes their knowledge', more recent sociologies of 
knowledge examine `how kinds of social  organization make whole orderings of 
knowledge possible, rather than focusing on the differing social locations and interests 
of individuals or groups'. 
The Classical Sociology of Knowledge
The nature of knowledge has been a central problem of philosophy at least since 
GraecoRoman times. Plato, for example, in Thextetus adopts a scientific approach to 
knowledge and cognition. The recognition, however, that knowledge in the broadest 
senses is contextdependent and somehow constrained by social factors is of more 
recent origin, as is sociology itself. Sociology could only arise after the dogma of a 
congruence between natural and social inequality had fallen into disrepute. The 
philosophers of the French and Scottish Enlightenment recognized that all social 
differences have social origins and are thus the result of factors subject to human 
control. They were aware that a wide range of social, economic and political factors 
share the genesis, structure and content of human thought, thereby anticipating one of 
the major propositions of the sociology of knowledge proper. 
In general, however, philosophers have attempted to demonstrate that a sociology of 
knowledge is neither possible nor desirable. Immanuel Kant thus argued that while 
there cannot be perception without conception, the constitutive components of 
cognition are a priori. Similarly, empiricists of various persuasions have maintained 
that scientific knowledge in particular is warranted by direct experience unaffected by 
social conditions. At most, these philosophies concede that extratheoretical factors 
influence the genesis of ideas but neither the structure nor the validity of thought. 
Otherwise quite different philosophies of thought have shared an often explicit 
rejection of the sociological relativism that is associated with the modem sociology of 
knowledge and have attempted to overcome doubts and skepticism by placing knowledge on a firm, uncontested foundation,  even outside the realm of sociohistorical experience. 
The modern sociology of knowledge, by contrast, investigates the interconnections 
between categories of thought, knowledge  claims and social reality - the 
Seinsverbundenheit  (existential connectedness) of thought (Karl Mannheim). Karl 
Marx was a significant precursor of the field, with his theory that under certain 
historical conditions economic realities  ultimately determine the ideological 
`superstructure' by way of various socioeconomic processes. This conception remains 
a central issue in the sociology of knowledge, and it has directly inspired some 
exemplary analyses of problems of cultural production, for example in the work of 
Georg Lukacs. 
Emile Durkheim, too, is an important pioneer of the sociology of knowledge, even 
though he failed to develop a general model of the classificatory process. Durkheim 
argued, especially in The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life (1912) and in 
Primitive Classification (1903, with Marcel Mauss), that the basic categories that 
order perception and experience (space, time, causality, direction) derive from the 
social structure, at least in less complex societies. Durkheim, Mauss and also Lucien 
Levy-Bruhl examined the forms of logical classification of 'primitive' societies and 
concluded that the basic categories of cognition have social origins. But they were not 
prepared to extend this kind of analysis  to more complex societies. Their basic 
assumptions have been heavily criticized,  but much sociological work continues to 
take as its starting point the Durkheimian proposition that the classification of things 
reproduces the classification of people. 
The classical sociology of knowledge owes its decisive development to the work of 
Max Scheler and especially to Karl Mannheim in the 1920s. It may be seen as the 
symptomatic intellectual expression of an age of crisis, and the recognition of its own 
rootedness in social structure and determination by social factors is perhaps its most 
characteristic trait. The mood of the German historical and social sciences during the 
period in which the sociology of knowledge developed in Germany may be described 
as one of 'tragic consciousness'. Georg Simmel's view of the 'tragedy of culture' as 
well as Max Weber's assertion that an inescapable process of rationalization leads to 
the disenchantment of the world and to new forms of bondage are symptomatic 
expressions of a period in which historians, philosophers and especially social 
scientists argued intensely about the issues raised by historicism, relativism, 
philosophical skepticism and the pervasive distrust in Geist. 
It is in this period that the sociology  of knowledge emerges as analysis of the 
regularities of those social processes and structures that pertain to intellectual life and 
to modes of knowing (Scheler), and as a theory of the existential connectedness of 
thought (Mannheim). Both orientations distance themselves from the Marxist critique 
of ideology which sees ideologies as mystifying representations of social reality and 
as disguises of the interests of powerful groups in society. The sociology of 
knowledge, by contrast, is concerned with intellectual and spiritual structures as 
inevitably differently formed in different social and historical settings (Mannheim). 
It was Max Scheler who first used the term  Wissenssoziologie (sociology of 
knowledge) a in the early 1920s and who, in Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge ([1926] 1990) provided a first systematic  introduction. Scheler extended the Marxist 
notion of substructure by identifying different `real factors' (Realfaktoren) which 
condition thought in different historical periods and in various social and cultural 
systems in specific ways. These `real factors' have sometimes been regarded as 
institutionalized instinctual forces, and as representing an ahistorical concept of 
superstructure. Scheler's insistence on a realm of eternal values and ideas, however, 
limits the usefulness of his notion of `real factors' for the explanation of social and 
cultural change. 
Karl Mannheim provided the most elaborate and ambitious programmatic foundation 
for a sociological analysis of cognition. Like Scheler he extended the concept of 
substructure, suggesting that biological factors, psychological elements and spiritual 
phenomena might take the place of primary economic relations in the substructure, 
but (just like the dominant theory of science) he did not think that scientific and 
technical knowledge could be subjected to sociological analysis. He investigated the 
social conditions associated with different forms of knowledge, and some of his 
studies are still considered first-rate examples of the kind of analysis of which the 
sociology of knowledge is capable. In addition to Ideology and Utopia ([1931] 1936) 
these include his analyses of competition as a cultural form, of conservative thought, 
of the problem of generations, and of economic ambition. 
Mannheim thought that the sociology of knowledge' was destined to play a major role 
in intellectual and political life, particularly in an age of crisis, dissolution and 
conflict, by examining sociologically the conditions that give rise to competing ideas, 
political philosophies, ideologies and diverse cultural products. Mannheim 
persistently pursued the idea that sociology of knowledge is somehow central to any 
strategy for creating a rapprochement between politics and reason, and this pursuit 
connects his various essays in the sociology of knowledge. Throughout, he believed 
that such a sociology has an important  transformative effect on its practitioners: 
sociology of knowledge calls intellectuals to their vocation of striving for synthesis. It 
changes their relationship to the parties contending in society, giving them distance 
and overview. But Mannheim's conception of the specific ways in which such a 
sociology might affect the state of political knowledge fluctuated and changed. There 
are three main versions: 
 1. sociology of knowledge as a pedagogical but also political mode of 
encountering and acting on the forces making up the political world; 
2. sociology of knowledge as an instrument of enlightenment, related to the dual 
process of rationalization and individuation identified by Max Weber, and comparable 
to psychoanalysis, acting to set men and women free for rational and responsible 
choices by liberating them from subservience to hidden forces they cannot control; 
and 
3. sociology of knowledge as a weapon against prevalent myths and as a method 
for eliminating bias from social science, so that it can master the fundamental public 
problems of the time and guide appropriate political conduct. 
The sociology of knowledge has in recent decades experienced a reorientation in the 
direction of an analysis of everyday life  and of natural scientific and technical 
knowledge (both neglected by the classical sociology of knowledge). Peter L. Berger 
and Thomas Luckmann's  The Social Construction of Reality (1966), written in the 
tradition of Alfred Schutz's phenomenology and Arnold Gehlen's philosophical anthropology, represents a distinct departure from the preoccupation of the classical 
sociology of knowledge with issues of epistemology and methodology. Everything 
that is regarded as knowledge in society is now accepted as a legitimate subject matter 
for sociological investigations. 
Inspired by developments in the history of science, the sociology of knowledge also 
turned in the direction of empirical analyses of the social construction of scientific 
facts, frequently by way of ethnographic studies of laboratory life. Such research on 
the `manufacture' of natural-scientific knowledge has led to a reassessment of 
traditional assumptions about the unique rationality of scientific knowledge. Seen 
through the lens of the `strong program' of the sociology of knowledge, scientific 
knowledge and everyday knowledge are in fact extraordinarily similar in certain 
respects. 
The Status of the Sociology of Knowledge in Sociology
The widespread and controversial appeal of the sociology of knowledge at the time of 
its inception owes much to the ambitious formulation of its aims, which go far beyond 
anything any other sociological specialty has ever claimed for itself. But Mannheim's 
project, while achieving considerable critical acclaim, nevertheless also foreshadowed 
the subsequent reception and transformation of the sociology of knowledge into a 
much narrower sociological specialty, as sociology itself evolved increasingly into a 
professional activity clearly differentiated from philosophy, history, anthropology, 
economics and linguistics," and as it became transplanted into other societies and 
increasingly reflected the commitments of disciplinary traditions considerably 
different from those found in Germany, where the sociology of knowledge had first 
articulated its intellectual and political mission. 
Even now, long after the ambitious program of the early sociology of knowledge has 
been moderated or even abandoned, and in  spite of its recognition as a legitimate 
sociological discipline, this recognition  itself remains impeded by the pervasive 
perception of the sociology of knowledge as a relatively marginal and often 'overly 
philosophical' and even 'speculative' sociological specialty. 
This observation can be corroborated, for instance, by the fact that the percentage of 
sociologists with interests in the sociology of knowledge had actually declined by the 
early 1980s, reflecting a perception that it  had somehow exhausted its intellectual 
resources long before its ambitious program was realized. This situation has recently 
changed, however. We are now witnessing a  renewal of interest in sociology of 
knowledge issues. The contributions in the second volume of this book document this 
renewal and the transformation of the  sociology of knowledge, its established 
boundaries, issues and solutions. 
In the remaining sections of this introduction, we discuss some of the reasons for this 
renewal and change of direction, focusing on some of the significant issues associated 
with the unusual history and status of  the sociology of knowledge. Rather than 
limiting ourselves strictly to one of the  contending models of the development of 
science, scientific disciplines or scientific specialties," we take up five themes that are 
particularly useful for illuminating the development and the intellectual status of the 
sociology of knowledge: (1) the origin  of the sociology of knowledge and its intellectual development and institutional  establishment within sociology; (2) its 
dogmatic history as presented, for instance, in textbooks, articles and essays 
reviewing its development and status; (3) the paradigm of the sociology of 
knowledge;" (4) its limits; and (5) its possibilities." Our primary concern is to 
critically review the representative attitudes  of social scientists with sociology of 
knowledge interests, since these views have until recently largely determined the 
evolution and status of the sociology of knowledge. 
Reconstructions of the Development of the Sociology of Knowledge
Karl Mannheim has provided us with a detailed analysis of the social conditions and 
processes that contributed to the emergence and differentiation of the sociology of 
knowledge. A comparable reflexive examination is absent from virtually allsubsequent efforts in the sociology of  knowledge, although there is an occasional 
acknowledgment that this may indeed be an important problem. Robert K. Merton, for 
instance, raises the question how such  a unique specialty as the sociology of 
knowledge, with its deep roots in German society and culture, was able to establish 
itself in North America in the first place, particularly since the receptiveness of North 
American social scientists and philosophers to the sociology of knowledge cannot be 
explained merely in terms of the immigration of German sociologists to the United 
States. Merton argues that American thought proved receptive to the sociology of 
knowledge largely because it dealt with problems, concepts, and theories which are 
increasingly pertinent to our contemporary social situation, because our society has 
come to have certain characteristics of  those European societies in which the 
discipline was initially developed'. However, Merton does not analyze in any detail 
the social crisis of the American society to which he refers, and one might argue that 
the immediate postwar period in North America, far from being characterized by 
conditions of social, economic and political crisis, was rather a period of continuous 
economic growth without major societal upheavals. It should also be pointed out that 
the process of dissemination and acceptance of the sociology of knowledge in North 
America involved its transformation. While it is known and even self-evident that the 
Nazi era in Germany represents a decisive turning point for the sociology of 
knowledge, the precise nature of its transformation has received far less attention in 
Anglo-Saxon countries, in particular in the United States. 
The North American transformation of the sociology of knowledge during the process 
of acceptance mentioned here begins in the mid-1930s with influential reviews of the 
English adaptation of Karl Mannheim's Ideologie and Utopie. These include reviews 
by Hans Speier in the American Journal of Sociology, by Alexander von Schelting in 
the American Sociological Review, as well as Talcott Parsons'review in the American 
Sociological Review of von Schelting's  Max Webers Wissenschaftslehre (Max 
Weber's Theory of Science) that deals at length with Mannheim's sociology of 
knowledge. These reviews are an initial (and,  in retrospect, successful) attempt to 
'normalize' the sociology of knowledge. A genuine sociology of knowledge must be 
what Parsons called a positive sociology  of knowledge by restricting itself to 
sociological inquiries into the formation of knowledge. 
While standard histories of sociology generally lack consensus about such issues as 
the origins of sociology, its major theorists and most significant achievements, and 
even about the issues warranting sociological investigation, accounts of the development of the sociology of knowledge are by and large fairly uncontested. The 
sociology of knowledge may be described  as having gone through three different 
phases of development. 
The first phase includes the theoretical approaches of the forerunners of the sociology 
of knowledge proper. Francis Bacon, Auguste Comte, Karl Marx and Friedrich 
Engels, but also Friedrich Nietzsche, Vilfredo Pareto and Sigmund Freud are 
commonly counted among these intellectual precursors or pioneers of the sociology of 
knowledge. 
In the second phase the sociology of knowledge was established as an independent 
sociological specialty. Max Scheler and  Karl Mannheim in Germany and, even 
earlier, Emile Durkheim, Lucien Levy-Bruhl, Marcel Mauss and Maurice Halbwachs 
in France, are the most significant figures here. And while infrequently identified as 
indirect contributors to the sociology of knowledge, the work of Max Weber, Georg 
LukAcs, John Dewey and George Herbert Mead, among others, should also be 
regarded as part of the history of the sociology of knowledge. 
This second phase is followed by a third that is recognizable in several contributions 
reprinted in this book. It might be called the phase of normalization, since during this 
period the cognitive domain of the sociology of knowledge is defined much more 
narrowly, the external relations of the sociology of knowledge are now mediated by 
disciplinary traditions, issues initially considered relevant are no longer considered 
sociologically significant, and, last but not  least, `solutions' to a number of initially 
unresolved questions are proposed. 
Such a normalization of the sociology of knowledge was achieved to a considerable 
extent by assimilating the sociology of knowledge to the then predominant conception 
of science in sociology, which interpreted the cognitive processes of science primarily 
in terms of a logical rather than sociohistorical point of view. The special 
epistemological status attributed to scientific knowledge contributed, of course, to 
sociologists refraining for the longest time from examining scientific knowledge 
sociologically." Only in the past three decades has a radical reorientation in the 
sociology of knowledge taken place in this regard, once again on the basis of 
philosophical reflections. Foremost is a revision of the traditional concept of scientific 
knowledge and of the theory of scientific progress. As a result, the epistemological 
vocabulary has become increasingly sociological. The effect of these developments in 
the philosophy of science, the history of science, and in a variety of substantive 
social science disciplines and specialties  (for example, anthropology and linguistics) 
on the sociology of knowledge has led to a reevaluation of its history and of the whole 
program of the classical sociology of knowledge.  
The Paradigm of the Sociology of Knowledge
Nearly all reconstructions of its paradigm agree that the sociology of knowledge is 
concerned with `existentially connected thinking' (seinsverbundenes Denken) or, even 
more generally, with an investigation of the relations between knowledge and society. 
In view of this comprehensive characterization of the scope of the sociology of 
knowledge, it is surprising that it ", should ever have been regarded as a mere 
'specialty' among other sociological specialties. Downplaying the significance as well as the implications of the sociology of knowledge has been one of the strategies in the 
attempt to legitimatize the sociology of  knowledge as sociology. If, just like other 
sociological specialties, the sociology of knowledge is legitimated by its specialized 
topic of inquiry, any far-reaching claims are precluded from the outset. Mannheim's 
attempt to transcend specialized sociology in the direction of a philosophically 
oriented sociology is, by contrast, an example of a more comprehensive 
understanding of both sociology and the sociology of knowledge. Mannheim writes: 
But what is decisive is that in Germany this possibility, which exists for 
almost all men now living - namely, to enlarge one's view of the world and 
to this end avail oneself of the method of sociology - eventually exceeds the 
problem area of this special discipline. The sociological problem 
constellation in the narrower sense transcends itself in two directions - in 
the direction of philosophy and in the direction of a politically active world 
orientation. 
And in regard to the epistemological  relevance of the sociology of knowledge 
Mannheim claims: `The sociology of knowledge, however, is in a position to provide 
a peculiar kind of factual information concerning the various truth concepts and 
epistemologies - factual information which itself has epistemological implications that 
no future epistemology may overlook'. 
The sociology of knowledge in the post-Mannheim period, by contrast, is 
characterized by an increasing renunciation of the general claims of the sociology of 
knowledge. This has led to difficulties. It is, for instance, problematic to claim that the 
sociology of knowledge is a mere sociological specialty among others, yet also to 
insist that its general objective is the analysis of the relations between knowledge and 
society, and that the relationship between thinking (or culture) and social processes in 
the broadest sense is constitutive of human thought and action. Issues such as the 
social causes of deviant behavior or the evolution of bureaucratic organizations can 
hardly be granted similar status and have comparable implications for general 
sociological theory and research. Mannheim himself argues pointedly: 'It is out of the 
question that a certain analysis should be stopped short once and for all at the most 
crucial point merely because the recognized domain of a different scientific 
department allegedly begins there (a mode of procedure typical of the bureaucratized 
organization of science)'." The stagnation of the sociology of knowledge in recent 
decades has no doubt in part resulted from the assimilation of its original concerns by 
general sociological theory, which no longer regards these issues as belonging to the 
sociology of knowledge. Lewis Coser observes: 
As the sociology of knowledge has been incorporated into general sociological theory both in America 
and in Europe, it has often merged with other areas of research and is frequently no longer explicitly 
referred to as sociology of knowledge. Its diffusion through partial incorporation has tended to make it 
lose some of its distinctive characteristics. Thus, the works of Robert K. Merton and Bernard Barber in 
the sociology of science, the works of Everett C. Hughes, T.H. Marshall, Theodore Caplow, Oswald 
Hall, Talcott Parsons, and others in the sociology of the professions and occupations, and - even more 
generally - much of the research concerned with social roles, may be related to, and in part derived 
from, the orientation of the sociology of knowledge. Many practitioners of what is in fact sociology of 
knowledge may at times be rather surprised when it is pointed out that, like Monsieur Jourdain, they 
have been `talking prose' all along" The incorporation and integration of the  issues of the sociology of knowledge into 
other sociological specialties," as assessed by Coser, also indicates that the sociology 
of knowledge cannot easily be seen as merely one sociological specialty among many 
others. The partial incorporation of sociology of knowledge issues by other areas, in 
particular by specialties with a history of extensive empirical research, is associated 
with a neglect of the foundational issues, in particular epistemological ones, that were 
considered extremely important initially. 
The central issues of the sociology of knowledge, according to Merton, include: 
1. Where is the existential basis of cognitive products located? 
2. Which cognitive products are subjected to sociological analysis? 
3. What is the correlation between cognitive products and existential basis? 
4. What are the manifest and latent  implications of such correlations? 
5. Under what conditions or at what point in time can these assumed correlations 
be observed? It is hardly surprising that the attempts to define existentially connected 
knowledge in concrete terms are characterized by a lack of consensus. The sociology 
of knowledge is, at least in this respect, self-exemplifying. To the comprehensiveness 
of its domain corresponds an abundance of proposed solutions to the central issues 
identified by Merton. 
Sociology of Knowledge and Its Limits
We have referred to the general research proposition of the sociology of knowledge, 
the thesis of the existential connectedness of knowledge. Most reconstructions of the 
sociology of knowledge are solidly agreed about the assumption that its analysis of 
human thought and ideas has to be limited to knowledge that does not qualify as 
`scientific knowledge'. As HansJoachim Lieber argues: in the sociology of knowledge 
the only subject of inquiry ought to be  `ideological knowedge'. Furthermore, the 
investigation of the relationship between specific ideas about reality and the 
existential connectedness of all knowledge,  'does not question the validity of these 
ideas, although the beginnings of the sociology of knowledge may indicate otherwise, 
since its interest was focused on the study of the social conditions of distorted and 
false knowledge and on a critique of ideology'. Coser refers to a third basic limitation 
of the sociology of knowledge: the issue of relativism and the logical contradiction in 
which a `radical general' sociology of knowledge inevitably becomes entangled. 
Referring explicitly to the Mannheim program for the sociology of knowledge, Coser 
explains that to him all knowledge and ideas, although to different degrees, are 'bound 
to a location' with the social structure and the historical process. ... From its inception, 
Mannheim's thesis encountered a great deal of criticism, especially on the grounds 
that it led to universal relativism. ... If it  is assumed that all thought is existentially 
determined and hence all truth but relative, Mannheim's own thought cannot claim 
privileged exemption. 
In spite of Mannheim's determined attempts to safeguard his own program from the 
charge of relativism, this charge has indeed been leveled against Mannheim himself: 
'Even where a dissociation from the Marxist suspicion of ideology is attempted', 
observes Lieber, a radical sociologizing of thought can easily succumb to relativism'. 
Most authors, however, have attempted  to avoid the problem of epistemology 
altogether. This is of particular significance in view of the emphasis placed by the 
founders of the sociology of knowledge, Karl Mannheim in particular, on this and related issues. Furthermore, it is precisely because of its epistemological claims that 
the sociology of knowledge initially encountered a frequently negative response." Part 
of the phase of normalization as a characteristic of the development of the sociology 
of knowledge in recent decades has therefore  been its intentional rejection of such 
issues. However, the traditional division of labor in science - epistemology here, 
substantive scientific disciplines and specialties there-thus sanctioned, and at the same 
time implied, the view that the majority of sociologists of knowledge fully agree with 
the critique against it by philosophers, epistemologists and others. The critique is 
thereby taken for granted, as not requiring closer scrutiny, for the sole reason that it 
deals primarily with issues of no direct importance to the sociology of knowledge as a 
sociological specialty. Niklas Luhmann has emphasized the sterility that can result 
from such a turning away from philosophical reflections. Screening out philosophical 
considerations [becomes], in turn, too confining. Introduced as a way of safeguarding 
research against an overwhelming tradition, the impermeable boundary between 
science and philosophy creates, now that the power of tradition is abating, thought 
barriers and provincialism, and frequently a too narrow interpretation of that which, 
indeed, is already being thought . 
The presumably neutral reconstructions of the sociology of knowledge are, of course, 
not the result of an unbiased attitude, but  rather an acknowledgment of widespread 
criticism of the sociology of knowledge as conceived by its founders. It is becoming 
increasingly evident, however, that  the separation of philosophical and 
epistemological issues from the sociology of knowledge creates an unreceptive 
attitude toward significant intellectual developments in other disciplines. To screen 
the sociology of knowledge from philosophy is quite compatible with the status of a 
sociological specialty. New developments in the sociology of knowledge, many of 
which are represented in the second volume of this book, indicate the beginning of a 
new phase which is characterized, in particular, by a gradual lifting of certain taboos 
which had been part of the phase of normalization. Developments in epistemology, 
which questioned the traditional concept of science and of the development of 
scientific knowledge, have been a crucial factor in this phenomenon. One of the 
results of the emerging concept of scientific knowledge is that in the sociology of 
knowledge the analysis of knowledge is no longer restricted to one particular area of 
human thinking. A sociology of scientific and formal knowledge, still questioned by 
the founders, is now considered a real  possibility. Similarly, the critique of the 
sociology of knowledge that for a long time had remained unchallenged, has itself 
become an issue for the sociology of knowledge. The problems of relativism, of selfrefutation and of the necessity for a distinct separation of the context of discovery 
from the context of the justification  of human knowledge is once again being 
seriously discussed. While there is even now bewilderment at hearing the term 
absolute, which also continues to fascinate, it is beginning to lose, once again, its 
status as an unassailable conception in the philosophy of science. 
The renewed interest in the sociology of knowledge transcends the classical sociology 
of knowledge program in other respects  as well. Importantly among these new 
interests figures a concern with what had been a shortcoming of the classical 
sociology of knowledge, namely the absence of a satisfactory theoretical solution to 
the question of how the relation between the structure of human groups and 
consciousness arises, is maintained or evolves, and therefore changes in the course of 
social evolution." One of the significant  areas of inquiry within the contemporary sociology of knowledge is therefore concerned with this very issue. Barry Schwartz, 
for example, has proposed an ingenious  solution to the 'missing link' in the 
Durkheimian sociology of knowledge by advancing a theory that accounts for the 
linkage between social conditions and classificatory systems. These developments in 
turn coincide with analogous attempts in  other disciplines or related intellectual 
traditions, for example with the attempts by Mary Douglas°' in anthropology and by 
Mary Hesse in the philosophy of science, to specify, often on the basis of empirical 
research in a variety of social science disciplines, what exactly is the nature of the 
relation between perception and social structure. 
But apart from such efforts, which often  occur at the level of a microsociology of 
knowledge, another important set of new themes and issues has emerged in the 
sociology of knowledge in recent decades. Especially significant are the assertions 
about the growing power of knowledge in industrial or postindustrial society (Daniel 
Bell, Norbert Elias), about the emergence of a new class (Alvin Gouldner), and about 
the increasing influence of a new caste of priests (Helmut Schelsky). These writings 
share a common emphasis on the growing  importance of specialized forms of 
knowledge in modern society and on the power that the carriers of knowledge may 
exercise. 
Prospects of the Sociology of Knowledge
Lewis Coser is one of the few commentators on the sociology of knowledge who 
considers the ambitious original claims of its founders a challenge rather than an 
obsolete burden. In his survey of the history of the sociology of knowledge he comes 
to the following pertinent conclusions: 
The sociology of knowledge was marked in  its early history by a tendency to set up 
grandiose hypothetical schemes. These contributed a number of extremely suggestive 
leads. Recently its practitioners have tended to withdraw from such ambitious 
undertakings and to restrict themselves to somewhat more manageable investigations. 
Although this tendency has been an antidote to earlier types of premature 
generalizations, it also carries with it the danger of trivializations. Perhaps the 
sociology of knowledge of the future will return to the more daring concerns of its 
founders, thus building upon the accumulation of careful and detailed investigations 
by preceding generations of researchers. 
The very question, however, whether such a return to issues that may have already 
been raised by the founders of the sociology of knowledge, and the related question of 
whether a transformation of the sociology of knowledge is in fact possible or fruitful, 
is not only the result of purely intellectual efforts but also, according to the theory of 
the sociology of knowledge, itself a development influenced by societal conditions. 
Merton, for example, emphasizes that an interest in the sociology of knowledge is 
determined by certain cultural and social conditions of society. One factor among 
these conditions is that with increasing social conflict, differences in the values, 
attitudes and modes of thought of groups develop to the point where the orientation 
which these groups previously had in  common is overshadowed by incompatible 
differences. Not only do there develop distinct universes of discourse, but the 
existence of any one universe challenges the validity and legitimacy of the others. ... 
Thought becomes functionalized. It must therefore at least be indicated  that the reconstruction of the sociology of 
knowledge by the generation of sociologists succeeding the generation of the founders 
discussed here coincided with economic, political and social conditions as well as 
academic and disciplinary circumstances which in their relative tranquility stood in 
marked contrast to the crisis conditions of the 1920s. The present renewal of interest 
in certain issues first articulated by the classical sociology of knowledge, in contrast, 
`reflects', as in the earlier period when it was first developed, the experience of a crisis 
in present-day society. In the concluding section of this book, Dick Pets, Volker Meja 
and Nico Stehr, Harvey Goldman, and Ann Swidler and Jorge Arditi analyze - from 
quite different positions - the `prospects' of the sociology of knowledge. 
Knowledge has of course always played a significant role in human life. Human 
action has to a greater or lesser extent always been steered by knowledge. Power, for 
example, has never been based exclusively on brute physical force, but almost always 
also on a knowledge advantage. At present, however, knowledge is assuming a 
greater significance than ever before. Advanced industrial societies are therefore 
regarded increasingly as `knowledge societies'. A thoroughgoing scientization of all 
spheres of human life and action, the transformation both of traditional structures of 
domination and of the economy, as well as  the growing impact and influence of 
experts are all indications of the rapidly increasing role of knowledge in the 
organization of modern societies. 
abuiyad

ليست هناك تعليقات:

إرسال تعليق